Friday, November 17, 2006
Deliberative Democratic Theory and the Citizens' Assembly
The focus of this week’s discussion was the concept of deliberative democracy, which is a pertinent concept when considering the Citizens’ Assembly (CA). What I aim to do in this post is describe the basic theory of deliberative democracy, discussing key issues like reciprocity and legitimacy. Applying these concepts to the case of the CA, I will attempt to illustrate ways in which the CA can be viewed as legitimate by the public at large, specifically through the use of reasoned arguments appropriate to the setting. I apologize in advance for the length of this posting, but the complexity of the subject matter and its relevance to the CA necessitates it.
Deliberative democracy is currently a major focus of study by political scientists and democratic theorists. Stemming from the philosophy of Jurgen Habermas, deliberative democracy emphasizes the role of communication and discussion in regards to politics and public issues. Its basic contention is that the best method of reaching the best decisions which everyone would feel were legitimate is through the ongoing defense and critique of public opinions through the reasoned arguments of active and engaged citizen-participants. As John Rawls puts eloquently,
when citizens deliberate, they exchange views and debate their supporting reasons concerning public political questions. They suppose that their political opinions may be revised by their discussion with other citizens; and therefore these opinions are not simply a fixed outcome of their existing private or nonpolitical interests.[i]
Accordingly, deliberation is seen as a means to produce results which, even if everybody has not been convinced of, everybody can at least understand the logic of and see as legitimate. It also is seen as effectively taking issues out of the realm of “private or nonpolitical interests” and made appropriately public in nature, an idea which I will develop later.
In their now canonical book Democracy and Disagreement, Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson outline a theory of deliberative democracy based on its capability to properly address moral disagreement in politics. Noting that deliberative discussion, even at the level of political elites, only occurs in reference to democratic procedure or in matters of interpreting governing principles (ie Supreme Court rulings), Gutmann and Thompson contend that the practice of deliberation should extend to what they call “middle democracy,” which encompasses “any setting in which citizens come together on a regular basis to reach collective decisions about public issues—governmental as well as nongovernmental institutions.”[ii] By extending deliberation to policy-making, administration and public reaction, citizens are put in more situations in which they are forced to defend their moral views to those who disagree, and are made to listen to opposing arguments and rationales. In doing so, “they express and respect [each other’s] status as political equals even as they continue to disagree about important matters of public policy.”[iii]
Gutmann and Thompson articulate three traits which democratic deliberation must possess in order to properly address moral dispute: reciprocity, publicity and accountability. Publicity refers to openness of argument, that moral claims and refutations are intended for “dissemination in public forums.”[iv] The notion of accountability indicates the need for those making moral claims to explain their claims to those for whom the reasons are offered. So, in current political life elected officials are (in theory) accountable to those who elected them, and therefore must defend their actions to the citizens. In deliberation, not only elected officials, but “ordinary citizens when they act in a public capacity”[v] (inclusive to participating in public deliberation) must be able to defend and explain their stances to other citizens. These two concepts, publicity and accountability, when taken in tandem point towards the third criterion of reciprocity.
Reciprocity refers to the method of argumentation, and essentially entails a respect for other citizens as politically and morally equal. Thusly, “reciprocity asks us to appeal to reasons that are shared or could come to be shared by our fellow citizens.”[vi] So, if in defending one’s moral stance a citizen cites his or her religious doctrine as a reason, he or she is appealing to reasons which other citizens not of the same religious belief could not reasonably, as free and equal citizens, come to share. Reciprocity also asks that “empirical claims in political argument be consistent with reliable methods of inquiry, as these methods are available to us here and now, not for all times and all places,”[vii] so that a claim and its supporting facts can be examined by other citizens, being open to scrutiny by other empirical claims. By making claims which follow the concept of reciprocity, citizens are making themselves accountable to their interlocutors and making their stances open to the public.
By this light, the CA is a legitimate deliberative body if it follows these three principles. To demonstrate how these principles might and might not be followed, an example is helpful. Say Bill is a member of the CA from Kapuskasing which is located in northern
In this example what deliberation can be seen to do is create public-mindedness in citizens. This is perhaps the most important and distinguishing aspect of deliberative democracy. Prior to the development of deliberative theories of democracy, the prevailing concepts of democracy fell into the category of social choice theory. Social choice theory, as Jon Elster explains, sees political views as determined by private interest, and therefore sees political participation as a private act. The political system then functions in a manner similar to the market in which individuals compete for their own interests, making the goal of politics “the optimal compromise between given, and irreducibly opposed, private interests.”[viii] Deliberative democracy differs in that it sees politics as a necessarily public realm. In this way, individual interests should not be aggregated and then a conclusive compromise be reached, but interests should be made into public interests in which all could discuss on the same grounds: “the core of the theory, then is that rather than aggregating or filtering preferences, the political system should be set up with a view to changing them by public debate and confrontation.”[ix] As I stated in the beginning of this discussion, deliberation makes political issues appropriately public in nature, by making the grounds on which citizens seek to justify their claims public-minded. Even if private interests are stated, they must be stated in terms of reciprocity, and in turn they are opened to exposure. Our previous example of Bill from Kapuskasing, illustrates this: while his interests might still be entrenched in his stance, he is still forced to appeal to the public good. Public-mindedness is forced to be brought out in deliberative bodies on the simple basis that individual-interest-based arguments will not move a forum brought together to discuss the good of the whole.
In these ways, the deliberations of the CA would are seen as legitimate if arguments conform to reciprocity and if the issues are discussed in terms of public-welfare as opposed to private interest. But legitimacy in this situation must function in two ways, both within the CA and outside the CA: even if the deliberations of the CA are reasoned and open, how might the general public see these deliberations as legitimate? This is characteristic of a question which has already come up on this forum, namely why should
The CA is emblematic of a departure from the more classical theories of deliberative democracy to the more contemporary. James Bohman writes of this transition,[x] noting that earlier democratic theorists dealt mainly with concepts of ideal speech situation, in which the actualization of something like Habermas’s ideal public sphere[xi] was the main goal. Currently, deliberative democrats deal more with making current institutions and procedures more compatible with, and open to, public deliberations. Bohman writes, referencing the more contemporary theories of Habermas, that “the only feasible form of deliberation occurs in the interaction between formally organized institutional decision-making mechanisms and informal and “anonymous” debates and discussion in the public sphere…it is this interaction via institutional channels…that makes deliberative politics possible, five the “unavoidable” constraints of complexity and the need for…law.”[xii] As such, the CA represents the opening up of electoral procedures and policy-making powers of the legislature to deliberative practice. However, the CA is hard to locate in the terms which Bohman lays out; certainly it is not part of the “institutional decision-making mechanisms” which the
Ideally, the vast majority of Ontarians would be involved in the process, making deputations and attenting consultation meetings, thereby integrating their views and arguments with those of the CA members. In this way the CA’s deliberation would contain the views of most of Ontarians, and in turn be viewed as legitimate by most of Ontarians. However, this has not been the case as of yet, and there seems to be no reason to suspect it will.
I would suggest that, similar to how arguments would be legitimate within its deliberations, the CA’s decision should be seen as legitimate based on the reasons, which follow reciprocity, it gives the general public for its decision (its decision being the question posed in the referendum). The general public can then agree or disagree with the CA’s suggestion and vote accordingly. In this way, if the reasons the CA offer do not convince the general public they are held accountable through the vote. But the suggestion would still be legitimate based on the rationale offered. According to this view, whether the CA is “representative” is not really important; the prime function of deliberation is to produce reasoned conclusions and any body, representative or not, might be completely capable of doing that. One might argue, as I would, that the merit and quality of the reasons and arguments the CA, or any deliberative body, offers might be directly related to how representative it is. For example, if the CA was composed entirely of Torontonians, not only would this not be representative of all
[i] John Rawls, “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited” The Law of Peoples.
[ii] Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement.
[iii] Ibid, 18.
[iv] Ibid., 15
[v] Ibid.
[vi] Ibid, 14.
[vii] Ibid., 15.
[viii] Jon Elster, “The Market and the Forum: Three varieties of Political Theory” from Foundations of Social Choice Theory” ed. Elster, J & Hylland, A. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986: 103.
[ix] Ibid., 112. According to this, Scholar84’s comprehension of the deliberative process as he states it in his recent Response to Young Ontarian is correct: “deliberative interaction…is different from this process because it should actually change the preferences of the opposing interlocutor, or the preferences of all interlocutors, if the resulting decision is a synthesis of two or more opposing arguments (something that is not possible with simple interest aggregation…), such that the new policy or prescription is supported whole heartedly and fully by all who deliberated on the topic.” The addendum to this might be that even if it is not “supported whole heartedly” by all, it could be by most, and seen as at least legitimate and logical by all.
[x] James, Bohman, “The Coming of Age of Deliberative Democracy” The Journal of Political Philosophy, Vol. 6, No. 4, (1998): 400-425
[xi] See Habermas, Jurgen. “The Public Sphere" in On Society and Politics, A Reader. Ed Seidman, S. Boston: Beacon Press, 1989: 231-237.
[xii] Bohman, 415.
[xiii] Here, J.S. Mill’s defense of freedom of expression, that the more opinions voiced the more likely the truth is to be revealed, seems particularly relevant. In this regard, representativeness can be equated to inclusiveness of opinions and viewpoints. On
[xiv] This view fits well into an argument I made early on in this forum that the CA capacity for representation was similar to that of statistics. The premise of the CA in this view was that any 103